International Journal of Integrated Care, 29 January 2010 - ISSN 1568-4156
Section on Conceptual Bases of Person-centered Medicine
Historical perspectives on person-centered medicine and psychiatry
Paul Hoff, Professor of Psychiatry, Deputy Medical Director, Department of General and Social Psychiatry, University of Zurich, Zurich, Switzerland
Correspondence to: Paul Hoff, E-mail: paul.hoff@puk.zh.ch
Introduction

From a historical and actual point of view, the idea of person-centered medicine is not only a question of our basic attitude towards the patient, but also closely connected with any particular concept of illness. WPA drew attention to this central topic already in its founding years and, together with other international medical societies, emphasized it again recently [1].

In general, the term ‘person-centered medicine’ can bear different, though strongly interrelated, meanings:

More specifically, different concepts of illness do have a significant impact on the way person-centered thinking is accepted and integrated into medical practice—or is not. Three examples shall elucidate this. They are taken from the history of ideas in psychiatry, but the arguments involved will be easily applicable to general medicine, as well.

Psychiatry as pars pro toto

The diagnostic process in psychiatry has always been a controversial issue. This has to do with particular features of this field: from all medical specialties, psychiatry and psychotherapy are most intensively connected with political, historical and social developments. Psychiatry, as we know and recognize it today, i.e. as a medical discipline closely linked with neurobiological, psychological, sociological and philosophical issues, may with good reasons be regarded a product of the era of enlightenment in the second half of the 18th century [2]. From this time on, the view of mentally ill people as persons gained influence, albeit slowly, as persons with indispensable human rights and with a personal autonomy that may be diminished, but not eradicated by whatever illness they might be affected by. Psychiatry began to emerge as a medical discipline, rooted in scientific research and dedicated to the treatment of individual persons.

Since then, three major approaches to the phenomenon of mental illness were developed and adopted in psychiatry: (1) the realistic[1]neurobiological approach from the middle of the 19th century until now, (2) the biographical-hermeneutic approach from the beginning of the 19th century until now and (3) the nominalistic descriptive-operational approach practised since the end of the 20th century by ICD 10 and DSM IV [3]. I will now discuss chances and limitations of these three concepts with regard to person-centered medicine.

These considerations are by no means ‘only’ theoretical, but they do have a significant practical impact on diagnosis, on therapy and on psychiatry's self-understanding. In forensic psychiatry which directly linkes the notions of mental illness and personal responsibility, the debate became especially controversial and attracted much public interest recently, although the arguments are not fundamentally different from those in the areas of clinical psychiatry and research [4, 5].

The risk of dogmatization

There are often underestimated risks for any of the three concepts mentioned above to be used in a reductionistic, not to say dogmatic way, especially with regard to person-centeredness:

In recent years, there has been a tendency to combine classical scientific areas with the suffix ‘neuro-’ in order to demonstrate the implementation of modern neuroscientific methods and results, e.g. in terms as neuroethics [12] or, more generally, neurophilosophy [13, 14]. In our present context the question arises if and how person-centered psychiatry could profit by this development. There are two arguments to consider: on the one hand, it is a promising new approach to combine neurobiological techniques like functional brain-imaging or neurophysiological data (e.g. evoked potentials) with more person-oriented areas as social cognition, decision-making or the relationship between affective and cognitive processes. On the other hand, just to combine different techniques or data will not solve the problems of the limitation of each method and the need of a leading principle ‘behind’ these single approaches. For example, the status of subjectivity or personal autonomy remains a tackling issue no matter which empirical procedure will be chosen.

Psychopathology and personhood

The reason for this is of a principal nature: the basic questions mentioned above cannot be answered by empirical research only, be it biological, psychological or sociological in nature. We do need a basic conceptual framework addressing the notions of personhood and mental illness in general, and diagnosis and therapy in particular. At this crucial point, psychopathology—once named ‘basic science of psychiatry’ (‘Grundlagenwissenschaft der Psychiatrie’) by Werner Janzarik (1979) [15]—might again become a relevant point of reference, but only under the following specific circumstances [16].

On the practical side, psychopathological notions will have to be continously developed further (e.g. by not taking any definition of delusion for granted, but to continuously link new empirical data with theoretical considerations). This shall include operational descriptions of psychopathological phenomena (e.g. within the ongoing development of ICD 11 and DSM V) [17] as well as ‘open descriptions’ (e.g. by scientifically respecting qualitative phenomena like personality traits, interpersonal traits or biographical aspects that are not easily detectable by highly formalized rating scales). And a close linkage, albeit not a merging (!), with neurosciences and social sciences will be essential (e.g. by further developing research designs for the interface between social cognition, empathy or altruism on the one side and brain function on the other side without accepting any naive reductionism or materialism).

On the theoretical side, psychopathology will have to acknowledge the chances and limitations of empirical methods (e.g. by the constant awareness of methodological fallacies, be they naturalistic or hermeneutic). It will need to accept subjectivity as a scientific topic of its own and not only as a temporary fill-in, which at some point of time in the future will be replaced by strictly neurobiological data and concepts. And, finally, it will have to actively implement historical knowledge about psychiatric concepts into the actual debate on psychiatry's identity (e.g. by reflecting upon the basic questions that link all the heterogeneous concepts of mental illness at least since the era of enlightenment, especially mind-body-relationship, nosological status of mental illness, status of psychiatric diagnoses, scientific relevance of objective vs. subjective data). But this will also mean for psychopathology to be self-confident enough to leave fundamental issues open (i.e. not to accept premature definitions of mental phenomena in general and of personhood, autonomy and subjectivity in particular, however, practical they may seem to be).

In a broader perspective it is obvious that, on the one hand, the notions of person or personhood are central issues in practical psychiatry, but, on the other hand, they necessarily lead us into the center of philosophical debate. And not too few psychiatrists, in history and nowadays, were and are decisively sceptical with regard to the benefits of such philosophical arguments for their field. However, if we do not want to reduce the notion of person to just one, usually the prevailing, scientific perspective, we will have to enter the debate on what is or what we call a person and in which way personhood can or cannot be affected by mental illness. One of the radical positions on this issue was developed by transcendental philosophers like Immanuel Kant and Johann Gottlieb Fichte for whom the concept of an irreducibly autonomous and responsible subject within his or her interpersonal relations was not (only) a matter of empirical science, but the prerequisite of any scientific approach to the conditio humana. These complex philosophical theories—and many others from the 18th and 19th centuries—have been criticized in recent decades, especially following the linguistic turn in philosophy in the 20th century and its usually underestimated consequences for psychiatry. But nonetheless the issue of personhood and its relationship to diagnosis and treatment of mental illness is far from being settled. So, if person-centeredness shall become the essential framework for psychiatry, the philosophical debate needs to be specifically reflected upon and integrated into psychiatry [18, 19].

Conclusion

In conclusion, these brief considerations on the history and present status of person-centeredness and on the future role of psychopathology can be summarized in three theses:

References
1.
Mezzich JE. Institutional consolidation and global impact: towards a psychiatry for the person. World Psychiatry 2006 Jun; 5(2):65-6.
2.
Hoff P. Emil Kraepelin und die Psychiatrie als klinische Wissenschaft. Ein Beitrag zum Selbstverstaendnis psychiatrischer Forschung [Emil Kraepelin and psychiatry as a clinical science]. Berlin Heidelberg New York: Springer; 1994. [in German]..
3.
Hoff P. Warum noch Psychopathologie? [Why still psychopathology?]. In: Schneider F, editor. Entwicklungen der Psychiatrie [Developments in psychiatry]. Heidelberg: Springer; 2006. p. 151-7. [in German]..
4.
Gruen KJ, Friedman M, Roth G, editors. Entmoralisierung des Rechts. Massstaebe der Hirnforschung fuer das Strafrecht [Un-moralize justice]. Goettingen, Germany: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht; 2008. [in German]..
5.
Kroeber HL. The historical debate on brain and legal responsibility—revisited. Behavioral Science & the Law 2007; 25(2):251-61.
6.
Churchland PS. Neurophilosophy: towards a unified theory of the mind-brain. Cambridge: MIT Press; 1986.
7.
Bickle J. Philosophy and neuroscience. A ruthlessly reductive account. Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers; 2003.
8.
Fulford KWM. Moral theory and medical practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1989.
9.
Jaspers K. Eifersuchtswahn Ein Beitrag zur Frage: ‘Entwicklung einer Persoenlichkeit’ oder ‘Prozess’? [Jealousy delusion. A contribution to the question ‘development of personality’ or ‘process’?]. Zeitschrift fuer die gesamte Neurologie und Psychiatrie 1910; 1:567-637. [in German]..
10.
Jaspers K. Allgemeine Psychopathologie [General psychopathology]. Berlin: Springer; 1913. [in German]..
11.
Hoff P. Erkenntnistheoretische Vorurteile in der Psychiatrie—eine kritische Reflexion 75 Jahre nach Karl Jaspers' „Allgemeiner Psychopathologie“ [Knowledge theoretical bias in psychiatry. A critical reflection 75 years after Karl Jaspers' „Allgemeiner Psychopathologie“]. Fundamenta Psychiatrica 1989; 3:141-50. [in German]..
12.
Greely H. On neuroethics. Science 2007 Oct 26; 318(5850):533.
13.
Bennett MR, Hacker PMS. Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers; 2003.
14.
Smythies JR. Neurophilosophy. Psychological Medicine 1992 Aug; 22(3):547-9.
15.
Janzarik W. Psychopathologie als Grundlagenwissenschaft [Psychopathology as a science of principles]. Enke, Stuttgart: Enke; 1979. [in German]..
16.
Hoff P. Do social psychiatry and neurosciences need psychopathology—and if yes, what for?. International Review of Psychiatry 2008 Dec; 20(6):515-20.
17.
Kendler KS, Appelbaum PS, Bell CC, Fulford KW, Ghaemi SN, Schaffner KF, et al. Issues for DSM-V: DSM-V should include a conceptual issues work group. American Journal of Psychiatry 2008 Feb; 165(2):174-5.
18.
Hoff P. Historical roots of the concept of mental illness. In: Salloum IM, Mezzich JE, editors. Psychiatric diagnosis: challenges and prospects. Chichester: Wiley & Sons; 2009. p. 3-14.
19.
Kendler KS, Parnas J, editors. Philosophical issues in psychiatry: explanation, nosology and phenomenology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press; 2008.
Notes
1

‘Realistic’ in an epistemological sense; i.e. the assumption that the real world is existing fully independently from our conceptualization or our mental acts; Emil Kraepelin's concept of ‘natural disease entities in psychiatry’ is the example for such a realistic approach to psychiatric nosology [2].